Stoning Modernity: The Challenge of Fundamentalist Islam

By

Okezie Chukwumerije

ngodo@msn.com

 

 

 

Time has a way of legitimizing all manner of human practices, which if they were newly invented would cause outrage. Ian Buruma

 

I love my aunts who were born twins. They are wise and worldly, and reassuringly comforting at those times when the daily grind of life weighs heavily on my shoulders. I adore them, and so do my relatives. Strange then to realize that had they been born several decades earlier, they would have been wasted at birth. For in my culture the birth of twins used to be considered a sacrilege and twins were consequently put to death at birth. To give birth to twins was to offend the gods; killing the twins appeased the gods and averted their vengeance. At the time no one doubted that killing twins was the right thing to do. It was a religious dictate, after all. A way of staying in accord with the gods.  Like those who shouted “Allahu Akbar” when Amina Lawal’s death sentence for committing adultery was affirmed, inhabitants of my village must also have celebrated when twins were put to death. Happily, for my twin aunts and for those of us who have had the joy and the privilege of knowing them, the civilizing conscience of modern society had swept away before their birth the odious practice of killing twins. Unhappily for Amina Lawal, and for those who consider her amorous activities a private matter between her and her God, the fundamentalist strand of the Nigerian Moslem population continues to reject the modernizing effect of liberalism and the distinction between private and public morality.

 

We owe to modernism and its enlightenment project our freedom from the bondage of tradition and history. The age of enlightenment, which was founded on reason, science, and respect for humanity, led to humanity’s emergence from millennia of darkness and ignorance. Where humanity was previously bound hand and foot by tradition and religion, modernism, with its emphasis on rationality based on experience and observation, liberated humanity. With modernism arose the desire to question, evaluate and reexamine received ideas and values, against the background of human experience, human reason, and human goals. No longer were historical texts, like the Bible, the Koran, and the writing of ancient philosophers, considered indisputable sources of immutable human values; the texts were a source of truth, but so too were human reason and evolving human experience. Modernism did not lead to an abandonment of religion or religious values. Modernism’s major accomplishment was to give us the tools with which to analyze tradition and received religious values, and with which to reconceptualize them in the context of our lived experiences as a community of rational beings.

 

Another important contribution of modernism was the creation of liberalism, a philosophy that emphasizes individual liberty, autonomy, and agency. Freed from the shackles of tradition and received values, each society was liberated to choose for itself the values and principles to guide its members. Furthermore, modernist thinkers like John Locke and Mill highlighted the need for individual freedom and liberty in a society of reason. Individuals were seen as having some inalienable rights in virtue of their standing as human beings. They could exercise their liberty and autonomy so long as they did not cause harm to another. It is within this tradition of liberalism, an admittedly western tradition, that contemporary fundamental rights and freedoms – of worship, of speech, of assembly, etc – were theorized.

 

Liberalism has also given us the public/private distinction. This distinction delimits the permissible scope of state regulation of individual behavior and actions. Within the public realm, the state can regulate the actions and conduct of individuals. For example, in most countries the activities of individuals while driving vehicles are considered to be within the public realm. Consequently, the state regulates matters relating to the operation of motor vehicles, such as speed limits, vehicle registration, and issuance of driving licenses. In contrast, actions or activities within the private realm are considered private to the individual and free from state regulation. The private sphere is an arena where the individual is free from government control, regulation, or intervention; it is an arena where he can be free to do as he wishes, accountable only to his conscience and to his God. The boundary between the public and the private is a heavily contested political issue, and the demarcation remains dynamic in most societies. For example, domestic violence used to be considered a private matter and most societies did not criminalize it. However, the educational effect of modern feminism has led to the reevaluation of the issue, and domestic violence is now one of the most policed issues in modern societies. Regarding the contested boundary between the public and the private spheres, the important thing to note is that in all liberal democracies the drawing of the boundary is a political, not a religious, matter. In liberal societies, it is the state, not religious groups or religious texts, that decides which activities or behavior ought to be regulated.

 

Most liberal societies are secular societies: they separate the state from religion. Freedom of worship is one of the core freedoms in liberal societies. Individuals are free to practice any religion of their choice and the state cannot improperly inhibit them in so doing. Furthermore, most liberal states do no entangle themselves with religion: they largely distance themselves from religious matters, neither inhibiting nor supporting the practice of particular religions. The rationale is to prevent state action from directly or indirectly inhibiting individual practice of faith. Britain is an aberration in this regard; for historical reasons the Queen, at the recommendation of the Prime Minister, selects the head of the Anglican Church. Nonetheless, in Britain, as in other liberal societies, the state is not bound by religious texts; neither can it improperly inhibit individual practice of religion.

 

The 1999 constitution is a liberal constitution. It guarantees basic rights and freedoms to individuals, emphasizes human dignity and freedom, and enjoins the state not to impede the exercise of constitutional rights and liberties, except where to do so is consistent with democratic and liberal values. Freedom of expression, religion, association, and assembly – the core freedoms in liberalism – are enshrined in the constitution. The freedom of speech and the freedom to practice ones religion implicitly acknowledge the public/private distinction by suggesting that certain spheres of human activity are inherently private and should, within limits, be free from governmental intervention and regulation. Art 37 of the constitution expressly recognizes this distinction by stipulating that the “privacy of citizens, their homes, correspondence, telephone conversations and telegraphic communications is hereby guaranteed and protected.”

 

It is against this background that one can see how the fundamentalist project of the radical wing of the Nigerian Moslem community undermines the promise of modernism and the benefits of liberalism. This fundamentalist project is designed first to blur and then to eliminate the distinction between state and religion. The ultimate objective appears to be to Islamize the society and to impose the Sharia legal system in all parts of the Moslem north.

 

I should state that there is no problem with any religious group proselytizing in any part of the country. Liberalism allows individuals and groups to practice their faith and prevents the state from interfering with this activity. The freedoms of religion, together with the freedom of expression, permit individuals and groups to proselytize their faith in any part of the country. In fact, the constitution expressly guarantees this right. The problem lies in cases where individuals and groups in a multi-religious liberal society want to foist their particular religion on the state and to use state institutions and authority to enforce religious values.

 

In evaluating the fundamentalist project, we should distinguish between Sharia personal law and Sharia criminal or penal law. Sharia personal law, together with customary law, has been recognized by successive Nigerian constitutions. Personal law relates to such non-penal matters as inheritance, marriage, and devolution of property. There is a case to be made for the reform of Sharia personal law to bring it in line with contemporary standards. However, some writers, such as Sanusi Lamido Sanusi who has highlighted the debate between modernity and tradition within Islam, have analyzed this issue with considerable depth and discernment. [I strongly recommend Sanusi’s classic article on this issue, “The Politicization of Ontological Questions: Discourses, Subjectivities and Muslim Family Law in Nigeria,” available at jamji.com]. My focus in this article is on Sharia penal law, and its effect on the liberal and modernist values embodied in our constitution.

 

It has been suggested that Islam is incompatible with liberalism. Here is what Sanusi Lamido Sanusi had to say on the issue: “The concept of a liberal state that is ethically neutral and whose task is to create an environment in which every citizen is free to pursue his/her moral preference without hindrance is rejected by Islam. Islamic ethic is metaphysical and does not recognize multiple versions of the truth.” If this is true, should we then give up on the idea of living together is our multi-religious society? The moral neutrality of the liberal state enables each individual to practice his or her religion, without state intrusion and without being force-fed the values of another religion. In liberal societies, religion is an intimately private matter. Consequently, people of different religious persuasions can live together in a liberal state, without fear of state-sanctioned persecution or discrimination. A liberal state does not necessarily recognize multiplicity of truths; what it does is to allow each individual to live consistent with his or her truth. If most religions are metaphysical and reject multiplicity of truths, it is liberalism that makes it possible for adherents to these religions to live together in a modern state. A Moslem can live consistent with his truth. So can a Christian. So can an atheist. Contrary to Sanusi’s conclusion, I believe that Islam is not inconsistent with liberalism, so long as each individual is permitted to live his or her own truth. The conflict arises when particular religious groups want to foist their fundamentalist religious views on the rest of society. Islam can thrive in liberal states. In fact, Islam thrives in the most liberal of states, America. It is the Jihadist strand in Islam that makes the religion appear incompatible with liberalism by seeking to eliminate the separation between state and religion. If Moslems can practice their faith in the quintessential liberal society (America), I do not see whey they cannot do so in an emerging liberal state like Nigeria.

 

Religions embody a moral outlook. They dictate how adherents should live their lives; they indicate how they can align their wills with the will of God. Most religious people are therefore constricted in their actions by their beliefs. They want to do God’s will, and God’s will is that enshrined in their particular religious text. Generally speaking, liberalism does not interfere with the ability of religious people to practice their faith or to do the will of their God. On the contrary, it is liberalism that makes it possible for all religious people to practice their faith in a multi-religious society. What liberalism prohibits is for particular religious groups to use the rubric of the state to proselytize their faith and to intimidate others to live in a certain way.  It does not take much to see that this prohibition is essential to the survival of multi-religious societies.

 

Sharia penal law in the north will lead to the elimination of the secular values of our constitution. Our constitution separates the state from religion. Although the constitution establishes and empowers Sharia courts to adjudicate issues of Sharia personal law, it nowhere permits the enactment of the broad scope of Sharia law in the way it is being done in some northern states. The constitution after all expressly enshrines the freedom of religion, and the implementation of Islam-specific criminal law, with its extensive intrusion into, and criminalization of, intimate individual behavior and actions, would inhibit the ability of non-Moslem people to practice their faith in states that have enacted Sharia law. The entanglement of state and religion in these states operates, at a minimum, to intimidate practitioners of other religions into behaving in ways dictated by a religion that is not their own. The enactment of punitive Islam-based sentences and the introduction of Islam-specific prohibitions are calculated to elide the distinction between state and religion.

 

Aspects of Sharia penal law are also at odds with the fundamental objectives of the Nigerian constitution. Article 15(1) states that the “motto of the Federal Republic of Nigerian shall be Unity and Faith, Peace and Progress.” Had the drafters of the constitution wanted us to be bound in eternity by the ancient cultural values enshrined in religious texts published hundreds of years ago, some of whose provisions do not even speak to the modern human condition, they would not have included the word “progress” in our fundamental objectives. For to aim at progress is to commit oneself to the reevaluation of cultural and societal practices based on lived and learnt experiences. Religion apart, does any one really think that stoning a person to death for adultery in this day and age represents progress? Unblinkered by religious doctrine, who amongst us would enthusiastically celebrate and blithely hail the stoning of an adulterer, in an age where adultery is pervasive and divorce common, and at a time when adultery has been de-criminalized in modern societies? Moreover, the drafters of our constitution were keen to the fact that cultural practices are not always commendable. This is why Article 21(a) provides that the “state shall protect, preserve, and promote the Nigerian cultures which enhance human dignity.” [Emphasis added.] This provision enjoins the state to promote those cultures that are consistent with human dignity. By implication, the state should have no business promoting religious and other values that are blatantly inconsistent with modern conceptions of human dignity. Vitally, the human dignity invoked by the constitution is not frozen in time; it evolves with the changing conscience and values of society. Stoning a person for committing adultery ill becomes a civilized country.

 

The constitutional prohibition of inhuman and degrading treatment conflicts with parts of Sharia penal law. Article 34(1)(a) of the constitution provides: “Every individual is entitled to respect for the dignity of his person and accordingly no person shall be subject to torture or to inhuman or degrading treatment.” This provision raises two crucial issues in relation to Sharia penal law. First, by what standards should we measure the dignity of the human person or what amounts to inhuman or degrading treatment? Second, do aspects of Sharia penal law contravene the prohibition of such treatment?

 

Regarding the appropriate constitutional standard, supporters of Sharia penal law would like to believe that the frozen, ironclad values of the Sharia should prevail. In their lights, if Sharia law states that an adulterer should be stoned, that ends the question. After all what could be more consistent with the dignity of the human person than religious law? Unfortunately, Nigeria is not a theocracy; it is a liberal democratic state. The values of the constitution are the values of the broad society, not those of sections of it, neither are they necessarily those of particular religious groups. Consequently, when we come to decide whether mandated Sharia penalties are consistent with the dignity of the human person, we are bound by the constitution to use the contemporary, evolving standards of our society. If it offends our collective sense decency to chop off a person’s hand for stealing a cow, or to stone an adulterer to death, then such practices are inconsistent with the dignity of the human person under the constitution, whether or not religious patriarchs, writing hundreds of years before our time, came to a different conclusion.

 

But wait a minute, are you not ignoring the lessons of postmodernism? Has postmodernism not taught us that values are contingent and often irreconcilable? Has postmodernism not taught us that the seemingly neutral process of determining societal values often conceal the power games played by those who make such decisions? We need not surrender to the moral relativism of postmodernism. True, values are usually in conflict. This is why the liberty and autonomy inherent in liberalism remains a core virtue in the postmodernist era. The state leaves us alone, in most cases, to live consistent with our values, provided we do harm to no one. But where a decision must be made on which values the state should enforce in particular cases, liberalism and secularism encourage us to look for what is common to the whole society, and not adopt wholesale the values of a particular religion. It is a plus that this process of searching for common values is political. In politics there is dialogue, engagement, and compromise. In religion, there is blind, often unthinking, faith in hackneyed doctrine.

 

On the second question, I personally think that aspects of Sharia penal law are inconsistent with contemporary notions of the dignity of the human person, both within Nigeria and internationally. But let’s not quibble about what I do or don’t think about human dignity. Let’s concentrate on the broader constitutional and philosophical issues posed by the broad enactment of Sharia penal law in Nigeria.

 

The Sharia prohibition of blasphemy may also be inconsistent with the freedom of speech enshrined in our constitution. The penalty for blasphemy under the Sharia is death. However, even when the constitutional guarantee of freedom of speech is constricted by state restrictions permissible in a democracy, there is no way one can reconcile this freedom with the capital punishment imposed for blasphemy under the Sharia. This is more so when one recognizes that the fundamental values of a modern liberal society like Nigeria are drawn not from religious principles but from rational conceptions of individual autonomy and societal interests. What offends, what outrages, religious institutions do not necessarily offend or outrage a liberal society. Therefore, the mere fact that a religious group considers a particular expression or act impious and blasphemous does not in itself warrant the suspension of the constitutional guarantee of freedom of expression.

 

In addition, the broad implementation of aspects of Sharia criminal law may possibly contravene our treaty obligations. International human rights law, for example, disapproves the lapidation of adulterers. In fact, the coalescing international position is the elimination of the death penalty and the prohibition of physical and cruel punishments, such as amputation and flagellation. Nigeria seems to be going the opposite direction by enacting the death penalty for trivial offenses.

 

Adultery in modern society is demonstrably ill suited for capital punishment. Rather than snooping around people’s bedrooms to see with whom they slept, the state ought to concern itself with devising creative solutions to serious crimes that plague society. If this penalty for adultery is vigorously and honestly enforced, we may well eradicate the problem of overcrowding and overpopulation in Nigeria, because we would quickly dispatch at least a quarter of our population.

 

Regardless of what one might think about the aggressive techniques of modern feminism, there is no gainsaying the fact that feminism has done a commendable job in unleashing the talent pool and creativity of women, a group that has hitherto been subjugated to men and oppressed in patriarchal societies. In most Nigerian universities there are now more women than men, and this is not due to affirmative action. Contributions of women are increasingly and refreshingly felt in the medical, the educational, the hospitality, and the business sectors of our economy.  These contributions are vital in an underdeveloped economy like Nigeria’s, where there is a great need for well-trained trained and educated workforce. Sadly, it is at this very period that we are beginning to appreciate the need to empower women that the fundamentalist strand of Islam in Nigeria has galvanized to clamp down on them. Using the penal system to segregate women, to put them in inferior schools, to force them to be subservient to men, and to lapidate them for committing adultery, will only inhibit the progress of the country. But then what these fundamentalists want is not progress; it is to revive the medieval culture of the Middle East in contemporary Nigeria. They want to overheat our liberal democratic process and then giddily watch as it deliquesces into a murky pond of unrealized modernist and liberal expectations.

 

It is reassuring to note that there are both fundamentalist and modernist strands in Islam. Sanusi has brilliantly illustrated this fact. If we want to sustain our liberal democracy in Nigeria, we should support this modernist strand of Islam in Nigeria. This strand makes the case for a contemporary reinterpretation of Islam and encourages Moslems to embrace the ideals of pluralism. We should not allow the fundamentalists to merrily harrow our liberal values and thereby to destroy our young democracy.

 

Modernism has taught us the importance of basing our values and systems of law on experience and observation, guided by reason; not on immutable and immemorial rules found in dated religious texts. Postmodernism has taught us that values are always contingent, rarely universal. You know “the” truth. I also know “the” truth. The problem is that your truth and my truth are not reconcilable. How then do we live together in the same country? Liberalism comes to our aid by allowing us, within limits, to live our own truths, and where state interests are implicated, it makes the resolution of contested values a political, not a religious, matter. Our mission as citizens in a liberal democracy should be to strive to reach agreements on societal values that can enable us live our lives as autonomous and free individuals in a world of diversity. Blurring the distinction between state and religion, muddying the boundary between the private and the public spheres, and foisting absolute and frozen doctrines of a particular religion on the state, undermine this noble goal.

 

Okezie Chukwumerije

San Francisco, California